Criticism of Theory of Forms
-
A review of the essential points of the middle period Theory
of Forms:
-
A "Two-Worlds" theory
-
A Form is a "one-over-many":
There's a Form whenever two or more things have something in common. Cf.
Rep. 596a:
We are in the habit of positing a single Form for each plurality of things
to which we give the same name.
-
Forms are paradigms
-
Things participate in the Forms by being appropriately related to these paradigms
(by resembling them??).
-
Participation explains predication (cf. Phaedo 100c):
A thing's being equal consists in, and is explained by, its
participating in Equality.
In general: x's being F is explained by x's participating
in F-ness.
-
A good summary statement is provided at 130e-131a:
"There are certain forms, whose names these other things have through
getting a share of them -- as, for instance, they come to be like by getting
a share of likeness, large by getting a share of largeness, and just and
beautiful by getting a share of justice and beauty."
-
The self-criticism of the first part of the
Parmenides:
-
How are these extraordinary criticisms intended to be taken?
-
As fatal objections to the Theory of Forms ?
-
As based on misunderstandings of the Theory of Forms that need to be cleared
away?
-
As prima facie problems for the Theory of Forms that demand modifications
of the theory?
-
My view: Some combination of (2) and (3) is probably closest to the truth.
Some of the objections are frivolous, but others are meant to be taken seriously.
-
The Setting of the Parmenides:
-
A discussion involving "the young Socrates" and the two Eleatics, Zeno and
his teacher Parmenides.
-
The Eleatics argued for monism, the view that reality is one:
a permanent and unchanging unity. In their view, pluralism, the view
that there are many real things, is false.
-
Socrates offers the Theory of Forms as an alternative to Eleatic monism.
It is put forward as a variety of pluralism that does not give rise to the
absurdities that the Eleatics find in pluralistic theories.
-
Parmenides and Zeno's reply is to attack the Theory of Forms, to show that
it leads to puzzling consequences of its own.
-
The Objections to the Theory of Forms:
-
The Extent of the World of Forms: What things are there Forms for?
-
Moral and aesthetic ideals: "just, beautiful, good"
-
Natural kinds: "human being"
-
Natural stuffs: "fire, water" [Socrates expresses uncertainty about groups
(2) and (3).]
-
"Undignified" things: "hair, mud, dirt." [Socrates denies Forms for things
in group (4), but Parmenides says that when he gets older he'll learn not
to be so fastidious. This is clearly a point where there is a conflict between
the role of Forms as (morally or aesthetically pleasing) paradigms
and their role as universals.]
-
The Nature of Participation
-
Part or Whole? (131a-c): The dilemma of participation:
Is (a) the whole Form, or only (b) a part of it, in each
participant?
If (a), then each Form will be "separate from itself" if it is in many things.
If (b), then the Form is divisible, and hence no longer a unity.
[The conclusion of this dilemma seems to be that Forms will either be
divisible or not shareable. But Forms have to be shareable,
that is the whole point of having the theory. So the consequences of making
Forms divisible is pursued.]
-
Puzzling consequences if Forms are divisible (131d-e):
-
The parts of Largeness are small (with respect to Largeness) but still
make the things they are in large. [Note: this conflicts with one
of Plato's requirements in the Phaedo: what makes something F
must itself be F.]
-
A part of Equality which is "less than Equality itself" nevertheless makes
what it is in equal.
-
The parts of Smallness are smaller than Smallness itself! And the
addition of such a part to something makes that thing smaller
than it was before the addition of that small part!
-
The Third Man Argument (TMA)
-
An infinite regress argument: "no longer will each of your forms be one,
but unlimited in multitude." (132b2)
-
The regress is epistemologically vicious.
The Theory of Forms is a theory of judgment (by "judgment" I mean
the mental state that is common to both knowledge and belief).
Judging involves consulting Forms: to judge that x is F is
to consult the Form F-ness and to see x as being sufficiently
like F-ness to qualify for the predicate F.
"The TMA is designed to reduce to absurdity the claim that it is the consultation
of forms which enables us to make judgments. It does this by showing that
if that were the case, we would have to perform an infinite number of such
consultations to make just one judgment." (Alan Code)
-
Since the Theory of Forms tries to explain predication, the TMA is
also a challenge to it as a theory of predication. (Recall our examination
of the Phaedo : the Form, the F Itself, is the aitia,
or explanation. of something's being F.
"Participating in a Form" is supposed to explain predication. And
the upshot of the TMA is that there is something defective about this
explanation:
Trying to explain predication in terms of the notion of participating in
a (paradigmatic) Form leads to an infinite regress, and hence is no explanation
at all.
-
The premises of the TMA:
-
Plato is not explicit about the premises of the TMA. We will have to reconstruct
the argument and tease out the implicit premises.
-
To start, let's try to see how the argument goes, and what features (or alleged
features) of the Theory of Forms are being brought into play. In the
table below, the steps of the "largeness" argument appear on the left; a
schematized version showing how the argument can be generalized appears on
the right. The horizontal line separates the Form (above the line,
the "one over many") from the things (below the line) that participate in
that Form.
The Steps of the TMA
Step One: We assume a number of things are (or "appear to us to
be") large. |
a, b, c |
Step Two: From this we infer that there is a Form (Largeness)
by virtue of which they all appear large. |
F-ness1
__________
a, b, c |
Step Three: We now consider all of the items discussed in Step
One (viz., all of the large things we were considering) and Largeness,
the Form by virtue of which they all are (and appear to us to be) large. |
__________
a, b, c, F-ness1 |
Step Four: From this we infer that they all (i.e., the
participants and the Form) participate in a Form of Largeness. |
a form of F-ness
_________________
a, b, c, F-ness1 |
Step Five: From this we infer that the Form introduced in Step
Four is a second Form (Largeness2), distinct from the Form
(Largeness1) introduced in Step Two. This second Form is the one
by virtue of which the first Form and all of its participants appear large. |
F-ness2
_________________
a, b, c, F-ness1 |
Step 6: We now consider all of the items discussed in Step Five,
viz., all of the large things we introduced at Step One, the Form we introduced
at Step Two, and the second Form we introduced at Step Four (and distinguished
at Step Five). |
___________________
a, b, c, F-ness1, F-ness2 |
And so on, ad infinitum.
-
By what principles do we proceed from step to step in this argument?
-
From #1 to #2: A principle that generates a Form for a collection of things
that all appear to have something in common (a
"one-over-many").
-
From #2 to #3: A principle that entitles us to group the Form together with
its participants as constituting a collection whose members all have something
in common. (Like its participants, the Form is something to which we can
apply the predicate "large". That is, a Form
can be predicated of itself.)
-
From #3 to #4: The One-Over-Many principle again.
-
From #4 to #5: What tells us that we have a second Form? That is,
what tells us that #5 shouldn't be written up this way:
Step #5
F-ness1
_________________
a, b, c, F-ness1
The question really amounts to this: What tells us that
F-ness1 and F-ness2 are two distinct
Forms?
Roughly: a principle which tells us that a Form is not one of its own
participants; that a Form does not participate in
itself.
-
So the argument appears to have three
premises. It has become traditional to call these "One Over
Many", "Self-Predication" and "Non-Identity":
-
(OM) There is a Form for any set of things
we judge to share a predicate in common. I.e.,
If a collection of things, a, b,
c, etc., are all F, there is a single Form by virtue of
participating in which they are all F.
-
(SP) The Form by virtue of which things are
(and are judged to be) F is itself F. I.e.,
F-ness is F.
-
(NI) The Form by virtue of which a set of
things are all F is not itself a member of that set. (Equivalently,
nothing is F by virtue of participating in itself.) I.e.,
F-nessn does not participate
in F-nessn.
The discovery of these as the three principles
underlying the argument is basically due to the ground-breaking efforts of
Vlastos [1954]. But his reconstruction of the argument
was flawed, since he had the idea that (SP) and (NI) actually contradicted
one another. This is important, if true: for if the Theory of Forms is committed
to both (SP) and (NI) and these contradict one another, then the Theory is
inconsistent! But Vlastos has been shown wrong on this. (Cf. esp.
Sellars, Strang,
Cohen.)
-
Reconstructed, Plato's argument looks like this (with the justification for
each step provided):
-
a, b, and c are all large.
premise
-
There is a Form of Largeness (Largeness1) that they all share
in. 1, OM
-
a, b, c and Largeness1 are all large.
1, 2, SP
-
There is a Form of Largeness (Largeness2) that they all share
in. 3, OM
-
Largeness2 is not identical to Largeness1
4, NI
-
a, b, c, Largeness1 and Largeness2 are all large.
3, SP
-
There is a Form of Largeness (Largeness3) that they all share
in. 6, OM
And so on, ad infinitum.
-
Self-Predication vs. Self-Participation
We must distinguish (as Vlastos did not adequately do) between these two
notions.
-
F-ness is F.
-
F-ness participates in F-ness.
Participating in F-ness is supposed to explain being F.
(SP) tells us that we can apply to the Form F-ness that very predicate
("F") whose application to sensible particulars is explained in terms
of participation in that Form. That leaves us with the problem of explaining
this case of predication: F-ness is F.
(NI) tells us that we can't explain x's being F by appealing
to x. Hence, the principle is really better called:
[But the label "NI", due to Vlastos, has stuck. It's important to realize
that it can be formulated in such a way that it doesn't contradict
(SP).]
-
The Role of the TMA's premises as principles of the Theory
of Forms
-
(OM) Predication is explained by participation.
-
(SP) The explanatory entity (i.e., the Form) is a
paradigm.
-
(NI) Explanations are not circular or vacuous.
What would be the consequences for the Theory of Forms of giving up one of
these principles?
Principle abandoned |
Consequence for Theory of Forms |
(OM) |
The theory becomes incomplete. |
(SP) |
Forms will no longer be paradigms. |
(NI) |
Some explanations become circular. |
-
Conclusion
-
The upshot of the TMA is that the Theory of Forms cannot provide a
complete account of predication by means of the notion of participation.
-
But since all three assumptions work together to yield the regress, why single
out OM? So long as Plato's theory likens forms to standards (in their role
as paradigms), SP and NI seem correct. OM should then be rejected on the
grounds that it is in the nature of a paradigm of F-ness that nothing
explains its being F. Rather, it explains other
things' being F. This means that there will always be at least one
"many" (at least one set of F's) to which we cannot apply OM.
-
What the TMA shows is that a paradigmatic theory of predication cannot be
both complete (in the sense of providing an explanation of every case
of predication) and non-circular. For the paradigm itself must bear the
predicate, and there we have a case of predication that the theory cannot
explain without circularity.
-
Plato's Reaction
-
How did Plato react to the TMA? This is a difficult question. We can make
some guesses based on the contents of later dialogues. (Our clues do not
all point toward a single answer.)
-
The Timaeus is usually thought to be a
later dialogue. And it contains the full-blown, unreconstructed Theory of
Forms. (But cf. Owen, "The place of the Timaeus
. . .").
-
Strang: Plato gave up paradigmatism and the doctrine
of recollection. He says (in Vlastos, Plato: A Collection . . ., pp.
198-99):
"In the interval between the second act [the middle period] and the third
[late period], which begins with the Parmenides, the paradigmatic
eidos and its brother, recollection, have been unmasked as impostors
and quietly buried. The TMA is offered by way of justifying the action taken
as technically correct. . .
"The more you become aware of, and enthralled by, the peculiar anatomy of
individual Forms, the fewer and the less important become the things that
can be said about Forms in general. They remain unchanging (Prm. 135C1),
if only to be the subject matter of timeless truths; they remain single
(Phlb. 14E5 ff.); but what they do not remain is paradigms."
-
Evidence from the Sophist:
-
Self-participation allowed? (cf. 255e, which seems to entail that
Difference participates in itself.)
-
Plato's talk of blending of kinds (a word he begins to use
more and more rather than the middle period's "Form" or "Idea") suggests
that he's starting to think of Forms as more like collections. This fits
well with Strang's idea: Forms as kinds are not likely to be thought of any
more as paradigms.
-
Plato abandons or modifies OM? Pol. 262d supports this: Plato contends
that it would be a mistake to think that non-Greeks constitute a real class
because they all have the common name 'Barbarian'.
References
Cohen, S. M., "The Logic of the Third Man,"
Philosophical Review 80 (1971) 448-475. [Jump back to
text.]
Owen, G.E.L., "The Place of the Timaeus in
Plato's Dialogues," Classical Quarterly n.s. 3 (1953) 79-95; also
in Studies in Plato's Metaphysics, ed. by R. E. Allen (London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul, 1965) 313-338. [Jump back to text.]
Sellars, W., "Vlastos and the Third Man,"
Philosophical Review 64 (1955) 405-437. [Jump back to
text.]
Strang, C., "Plato and the Third Man," Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. vol. 37 (1963) 147-164; also in Plato:
A Collection of Critical Essays, vol. 1, ed. by G. Vlastos (New York:
Anchor, 1971) 184-200, and on reserve in OUGL. [Jump back to
text.]
Vlastos, G., "The Third Man Argument in the
Parmenides," Philosophical Review 63 (1954) 319-349; also in Studies
in Plato's Metaphysics, ed. by R. E. Allen (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1965) 231-263. [Jump back to text.]
Go to next lecture
on Plato's Cosmology: The Timaeus
Go to previous
lecture on the "One Over Many" Argument
Need a quick
review of the Theory of Forms? Click here.
Return to the PHIL 320 Home Page
Copyright © 2000, S. Marc Cohen
-
This page was last updated on 11/12/00.