-
This is a book about ontology ("what there is") and predication (what it
is to say something about something that there is).
-
Ontology: The Ten Categories
In the Categories, we get this list (1b25):
-
Substance
-
Quality
-
Quantity
-
Relation
-
Where
-
When
-
Position
-
Having
-
Action
-
Passion
This is presumably a list of the ten fundamentally different kinds of things
that there are. The first category - substance - is the most important in
Aristotle's ontology. Substances are, for Aristotle, the fundamental entities.
To see why this is so, we will have to understand what Aristotle says about
predication.
-
Predication
-
A subject (hupokeimenon) is what a statement is about.
-
A predicate (katêgoroumenon) is what a statement says
about its subject.
Examples:
-
This (particular animal) is a man.
-
Man is an animal.
-
This (particular color) is white.
-
White is a color.
The same thing may be both a subject and a predicate, e.g., man and
white above. Some things are subjects but are never predicates, e.g.,
this (particular) animal, or this (particular) color.
-
Two kinds of predication
Consider the following pair of simple (atomic) sentences:
-
"Socrates is a human being"
-
"Socrates is wise"
Do both of these atomic sentences have the same kind of ontological
underpinning? I.e., is the structure of the fact that Socrates is a man
the same as the structure of the fact that Socrates is wise? Plato's account
suggests that it is.
-
For Plato:"x is F" means that x partakes of the Form,
F-ness.
For Plato, predication, in general, is explicated in terms of the notion
of participating in a Form. In response, Aristotle thinks this
oversimplifies. For Aristotle:
-
"Socrates is a human being" tells us something fundamental about what kind
of a thing Socrates is: it is an essential predication.
-
"Socrates is wise" tells us something less fundamental, something that merely
happens to be the case: it is an accidental predication.
This idea emerges in the Categories distinction between what is said
of a subject and what is in a subject, introduced as part
of the four-fold distinction drawn at 1a20.
-
Two fundamental relations: SAID OF and IN a subject.
There are two basic ontological relations that cut across all ten categories.
These correspond to the notions (that Aristotle later develops) of
essential and accidental predication.
-
SAID OF a subject
-
This is a relation of fundamental ontological classification. It is
the relation between a kind and a thing that falls under it.
-
It is a transitive relation (i.e., if x is SAID OF y
and y is SAID OF z, it follows that x is SAID OF
z).
-
Its relata belong to the same category. A universal in a given category
is SAID OF the lower-level universals and individuals that fall under it.
Examples:
-
Man is SAID OF Socrates.
-
Animal is SAID OF man.
-
(Hence) animal is SAID OF Socrates.
-
White is SAID OF this (particular) color.
-
Color is SAID OF white.
-
IN a subject
-
This is a relation of fundamental ontological dependence. What is
IN a subject, Aristotle says, belongs to it "not as a part, and cannot exist
separately from what it is in" (1a24).
-
This is a cross-categorial relation; things IN a subject are
non-substances; the things they are IN are substances: non-substances
are IN substances.
Examples:
-
This grammatical knowledge is IN a soul.
-
This white is IN a body.
-
Color is IN body.
-
Universals and Particulars
Although Aristotle does not use these terms in the Categories,
it is clear that he intends to capture the notions of universal and particular
with his SAID OF locution:
-
Category Trees:
-
Each category can be thought of as having a tree structure. The category
itself can be divided into its fundamental kinds (e.g., substance
can be divided into plants and animals). Each of these kinds can in turn
be divided (e.g., animal can be divided into the various broad genera
of animals). Each of these can in turn be divided into the fundamental species
of the category in questions (e.g., into such basic kinds as tiger,
and horse, and human being). Finally, we can divide these
lowest-level kinds into the basic individuals in the category (e.g., human
being can be divided into Socrates, Callias, Coriscus, etc.).
-
Similarly, the category of quality can be divided into subcategories
such as color, which can in turn be divided into red,
green, etc. Aristotle thinks that these specific qualities can be
further divided into individuals (analogous to individual substances) such
as this individual bit of white.
-
Thus, each category is ultimately divisible into the individual members
of that category.
-
The fourfold division (Categories, Ch. 2)
The SAID OF relation divides entities into universals and particulars; the
IN relation divides them into substances and non-substances. Hence, the fourfold
division at 1a20ff produces (in Aristotle's order of presentation):
-
Universal substances
-
Particular non-substances
-
Universal non-substances
-
Particular substances
The chart below summarizes the fourfold division of Aristotle's ontology:
The Ontology of Aristotle's
Categories
(a) SAID OF a subject
not IN a subject
man, horse, animal
Universal Substances |
(c) SAID OF a subject
IN a subject
knowledge, white
Universal non-Substances
|
(d) not SAID OF a subject
not IN a subject
this man,
this horse
Individual Substances
|
(b) not SAID OF a subject
IN a subject
this knowledge of grammar,
this white
Individual non-Substances
|
-
Cross-categorial predication
-
Predication within a category ("Socrates is a human," "a tiger is an animal,"
"red is a color") involves classifying something (whether a particular
or a universal) under some higher universal within the same category
tree. Predication is a matter of classification.
-
Cross-categorial predication ("Socrates is wise," "This horse is white")
is more complicated. Here we are predicating an accident (something
IN a subject) of a substance in which it inheres.
-
Are such (accidental) predications still a matter of classification? Yes.
But we are classifying something IN a substance, rather than the substance
itself.
-
Example: "This horse is white" classifies a particular bit of color, inhering
in this horse, under the color-universal white.
-
That is: White is SAID OF an individual bit of color that is IN this
horse.
-
Primary Substances: the basic individuals
Things that are neither SAID OF nor IN any subject Aristotle calls "primary
substances" (protai ousiai).
Primary substances are fundamental in that "if they did not exist it would
be impossible for any of the other things to exist" (2b5).
-
Aristotle's argument for the ontological priority of primary substances
(2a34-2b7)
-
Every secondary (universal) substance is predicated of (i.e., SAID OF) some
primary substance or other.
-
Every non-substance (whether universal or particular) is IN some primary
substance or other.
-
That is, everything other than primary substance is either SAID OF or IN
primary substances.
-
Therefore, if primary substances did not exist, neither would anything else.
-
Comparison with Plato
-
The ontological priority is reversed. For Plato, particulars (participants
in Forms) are the dependent entities; the Forms in which they participate
are the independent entities. For Aristotle, it is individuals that are
ontologically primary or basic.
-
Aristotle has two kinds of predication relation; Plato's theory, although
less clearly articulated, seems to have only one.
-
The difference can be seen most clearly if we read Aristotle's
Categories as a response to the dilemma of participation that
Plato brings up in the Parmenides.
-
The dilemma of participation
-
Here's Plato's presentation of the problem (Parm. 131a-c):
Do you think, then, that the form as a whole - one thing - is in each
of the many ... so, being one and the same, it will be at the same time,
as a whole, in things that are many and separate, and thus it would be separate
from itself?
Socrates replies with the suggestion that a Form may be "in" many things
in the way that many people may all be covered with one sail. To which Parmenides
replies:
In that case, would the sail be, as a whole, over each person, or would
a part of it be over one person and another part over another? ["A part,"
Socrates replies.] So the forms themselves are divisible, Socrates, and
the things that partake of them would partake of a part; no longer would
a whole form, but only a part of it be in each thing.
-
As Plato has Parmenides present the dilemma, both horns are unattractive:
-
If the whole Form is in each participant, then the Form will be "separate
from itself," which seems impossible.
-
If only a part of each Form is in each participant, then the Form will be
many, and not one, which also seems impossible. (An even more important problem,
that Plato does not mention: if two different participants have two
different things in them, what makes them have one and the same
thing in common? The theory will not explain what it is supposed to.)
-
Aristotle's solution goes between the horns of this dilemma: it is not precisely
correct to say that the whole universal is in each particular of which it
is predicated, nor is it precisely correct to say that it is "only" a part
of the universal that is in a given particular.
-
On Aristotle's account: white (the genus or universal) is SAID OF
the particular color that is IN this horse. So, for one and the same thing,
whiteness, to be in both this horse and that horse (Plato's problem case)
is just for the color of this horse and the color of that horse both to be
classified as white. (White is SAID OF both of these two individual
instances of color.) Whiteness is therefore in both horses without being
"separate from itself" for it is just the common classification of the particular
bits of color in them both.
-
According to Aristotle, what is IN individual substances is, ultimately,
individual. But just as individual substances can be classified under universals
(like horse and animal), so too can the qualities, etc., of
substances be classified under universals (like white and
color).
-
For more detail on this interpretation of Aristotle's Categories as
a response to Plato's Dilemma of Participation, see Matthews and Cohen,
"The One and the Many" p. 644, on reserve.
-
Substances and Change
In Cat. 5, Aristotle points out the hallmarks of substance, one of
which is that substances are the subjects that undergo change ["Most
characteristic of substance seems to be the fact that something one and the
same in number can receive contraries" (4a10).]
Thus in the ontology of the Categories, substances are the
continuants - the individuals that persist through change remaining
one and the same in number. But, as we will see, Aristotle's investigation
of the topic of change begins to exert pressure on this ontology. A claimant
(viz., matter) will emerge to challenge the place of individual plants
and animals as the basic subjects of predication and change.