The Greeks are wrong to accept coming to be and perishing, for no thing
comes to be, nor does it perish, but they are mixed together from things
that are and they are separated apart. And so they would be correct to call
coming to be being mixed together, and perishing being separated
apart.
Why does he hold this? Cf. Robinson (p. 176):
According to Empedocles, bone is made up of earth, air, fire, and water,
blended in a certain proportion. It should be possible, therefore, to break
it down again into these elements. The difficulty is that when this is done
the bone ceases to be bone any longer; and if Parmenides is right, this is
impossible. If bone is, it cannot cease to be.
For how could hair come from not hair or
flesh from not flesh?
Anaxagoras sought to evade this difficulty by insisting that bone is homoiomerous, i.e., made up of parts having the same nature as the whole. No matter how far it is broken down, what remains is bone.
Bone is not made up of other elements. Every part of bone has the same nature as the whole. Every part of bone is bone; every part of gold is gold, etc. This is Anaxagoras's notorious principle of Homoiomereity (or uniformity, lit. "like-partedness"):
(H) Every part of any kind of stuff, S, is itself S.
It is controversial whether Anaxagoras maintained (H), which is not asserted
in any fragments. There is evidence for it in the testimonia, however. Cf.
Aristotle's summaries in 26 and 27.
Anaxagoras seems to have felt that Empedocles had not gone far enough. If everything consisted solely of the four elements, then in putting together the four elements in different proportions to form, say, flesh or bone, Empedocles had not, to Anaxagoras's mind, succeeded in eliminating the coming-into-being of something new. The only way to do that was to posit in everything the presence ab initio of everything which might emerge from it.
So Anaxagoras's principle (H) is designed to enable him to deny the existence
of real generation and destruction.
What is more, Anaxagoras seems to have imagined that there are no limits on what kinds of changes are possible. That is, anything can come from anything. This leads to the principle of Universal Mixture (12, cf. also 7):
In everything there is a portion of everything ....
This is most plausibly construed as a principle about kinds of stuff (cf. Barnes, The Presocratics, pp 320-323):
(UM) For any kinds of stuffs, S, S': in each piece of S there is a portion of S'.
That is, every piece of gold contains portions of wood, flesh, hair, water,
silver, etc. Anaxagoras's principle (UM) is designed to enable him to allow
for the existence of real change without allowing for real generation
and destruction.
Anaxagoras's theory of matter rests on two propositions which seem flatly
to contradict one another. One is the principle of homoiomereity: a natural
substance such as a piece of gold consists solely of parts which are like
the whole and like one another - every one of them gold and nothing
else. The other is: "There is a portion of everything in everything," understood
to mean that a piece of gold . . . so far from containing nothing but gold,
contains portions of every other substance in the world.
This is Anaxagoras's principle of Infinite Divisibility. There are
no atoms. This means that we will never reach a part, P*, about which
we get the contradictory result that it contains no parts but still satisfies
(UM).
The distinction between parts and portions is one that only a non-atomist
can coherently make. The idea is simple. Suppose we mix flour, water, chocolate,
and eggs together, and bake them into a cake. There is a portion of flour
in the cake, and a portion of eggs, etc. But no matter how finely we divide
the cake up, we will not recover the flour or the eggs. As Anaxagoras would
say, "every part of the cake is cake." We are not forced to say whether the
ultimate particles we arrive at are cake-particles or flour-particles, for
there are no ultimate particles making up the cake.
So the reason why there can be silver in a lump of gold, L, even though every
part of L is gold, is that not every portion is a part. There are
portions of silver, etc., in L even though every part of L
is gold.
(H) tells us that every part of S is itself S.
(Every part of the cake is cake.)
(UM) tells us that for every pair of kinds of stuff, S and S', there is a portion of S in S'.
(There is a portion of every kind of stuff in the cake. And there is a portion
of every kind of stuff in every part of the cake. But every part of
the cake is cake.)
(P) Each kind of stuff is called after the ingredient of which it contains most.
Cf. 25 (= Aristotle, Phys. 187b2-6).
... things appear to differ from each other and are called by different
names from one another based on what is most predominant in extent in the
mixture of the infinitely many [components]. Nothing is purely or as a whole
pale or dark or sweet or flesh or bone, but whatever each contains the most
of is thought to be the nature of that thing.
It is true to say that we cannot give an account of substances such as
gold by analyzing them into "a predominance of gold" and so on to infinity.
In such a case we have failed to give either a satisfactory definition or
a satisfactory account of gold because we have included the term gold in
our attempts at definition and description. But it is not an objection to
any position maintained by Anaxagoras, as he had no reason to attempt a
definition or a description of gold in this way. He is concerned with change
and not with description or definition.
One reason Anaxagoras maintained (UM) was to account for our ability to take in nourishment. We eat wheat, and our flesh increases. When we eat too many chocolate chip cookies, our bodies bulk up with flesh, not with chocolate chip cookies. The idea is that we extract the flesh already present in the food we eat. An ancient scholiast describes the theory (Aetius, A46, not reprinted in RAGP):
We take in nourishment that is simple and homogeneous, such as bread or water, and by this are nourished hair, veins, arteries, flesh, sinews, bones and all the other parts of the body. Which being so, we must agree that everything that exists is in the nourishment we take in, and that everything derives its growth from things that exist. There must be in that nourishment some parts that are productive of blood, some of sinews, some of bones, and so on - parts which reason alone can apprehend.
But notice that the theory of nutrition requires that wheat contain not just portions of flesh, but physically removable parts that are flesh. Unless the flesh that's in the wheat (as a part, or a portion - i.e., in the wheat in some sense of "in") can be extracted and join the flesh of the body, then one's flesh will not, according to the theory, bulk up from eating wheat.
But if the wheat contains removable parts that are flesh, principle (H) seems to collapse: not every part of wheat will be wheat. Some parts will be flesh.
One might think to save Anaxagoras by appealing to (UM). For any fleshy part of the wheat that is extracted will, by (UM), contain portions of everything, including wheat. So even the fleshy parts of the wheat are still, at least in part, wheat.
But this will not do. For (P) tells us that only a mixture in which wheat
predominates is wheat. If wheat is only a minority ingredient in some
fleshy part, then that part is flesh and not wheat. A minority element
in a mixture does not contribute to the determination of the nature of that
mixture. (H) and (P) together entail that flesh must predominate in all of
the homoiomerous parts of flesh.
(H), (UM), and (P) are logically consistent: they do not entail a contradiction. But our way of showing them to be consistent reveals that they are incompatible with the theory of nutrition that has been attributed to him.
{(H), (UM), (P), + Anaxagoras's theory of nutrition} leads to a contradiction.
Go to previous lecture on Empedocles
Return to the PHIL 320 Home Page